1.1 In the new Egypt, where the
Muslim Brotherhood and other Islamists are the targets of a broad and
massively popular campaign of arrest, exclusion and vilification,
it's fashionable to repeat the old mantra of the Egyptian security
state that religion and politics either are or should be separate
domains of human activity. Many of those who argue this case oppose the formation of political parties with overtly
religious or sectarian agendas. The arguments in favour of this
position include the following:
1.2.1 Religion and politics do not
mix because religion is about a human being's relationship with God
and with other human beings at the individual, personal level, and
not about the way society at large or the formal state is structured
and managed. God and/or the founders of Islam (or any other religion)
never intended their ideas to be the blueprint for any political
agenda.
1.2.2 Religion and politics do not
mix because giving religion a place in politics empowers the
traditional arbiters of religious orthodoxy, who are mostly a group
of reactionary, misogynistic, intolerant and puritanical men out of
touch with the 'modern' world and the needs and desires of ordinary
people.
1.2.3 Religion and politics do not
mix because giving religious hierarchies a political role could be
undemocratic because they might intervene in political decisions or
legislative deliberations on the basis of their understanding of
God's will, in contravention of the popular will as expressed in
elections or by other means.
1.2.4 Religion and politics do not
mix because political parties that advocate policies based on
religion (such as the imposition of some version of Islamic sharia,
for example) are socially divisive. Such parties automatically
exclude people of other faiths (in the Egyptian case, Christians,
Jews, Baha'is, atheists and so on).
1.2.5 Religion and politics do not
mix because those who use religious slogans, imagery and other
references in their political campaigning have an unfair advantage
over those who do not, because these references resonate powerfully
with ignorant, ill-educated people (whose votes have the same weight
as those of 'more rational' people)
2.1 At first sight, some of these
arguments might appear persuasive. They have certainly been common
currency in political discourse in Egypt and many other
Muslim-majority countries for many decades. The arguments do however
imply certain assumptions that advocates might not have thought out
thoroughly or articulated in public. These probably include the
following:
2.2.1 The assumption that God has no
interest in public affairs, that God sees a qualitative difference
between caring about those you know and caring about those members of
the wider community that you do not know. The implication is that God
wants you to be charitable to your neighbour, for example, but He
doesn't think you should take a position on whether the state spends
your tax money on health care or on palaces for the president. God
wants you to settle your differences with your mother-in-law amicably
but He doesn't care whether or not your state goes to war with a
neighbouring state.
2.2.2. The assumption that the
traditional religious hierarchy – monolithic and impervious to
change - represents either, at best, an unrealistic ideal that no
politician should even seek to attain or implement or, at worst, a
misguided and distorted version of the true will of God, that
religions make excessive demands on believers and for the sake of
expediency it is best to ignore or overrule religious prescriptions
that would complicate public life. The Muslim hierarchy condemns
interest payments, for example, but the need to be part of a world
economy that depends on interest overrides the ban that the hierarchy
would like to impose.
2.2.3 The assumption that sectarian
identities are rigid, with impermeable barriers, and that it is
undesirable to debate differences of opinion on religious matters in
public. Under this schema the religious hierarchy cannot be
challenged directly: the dissident believer's only recourse is to opt
out of the debate.
2.2.4 The assumption that political
parties should meet a higher standard of inclusivity than religious
groups, which may legitimately restrict their membership or their
message to people favourable to a certain ideology.
2.2.5 The assumption that there is
a qualitative difference between the political choices made by
religious people and those made by non-religious people, and that
emotional appeals to abstract non-religious principles or 'values' –
such as nationalism, class interest, social justice, liberation from
oppression, for example – are more acceptable than appeals to
religious sensibility.
3.1 I'm an agnostic, so I cannot
rule on the validity of, for example, assumption 2.2.1 (that God has
no interest in public affairs) or assumption 2.2.2 (that the
religious hierarchy is misguided). But when large numbers of people
accept these assumptions it has important implications for the health
and smooth functioning of society as a whole, in the following ways:
3.2.1 (in response to assumption 2.2.1)
Quietism, the belief that God wants us to withdraw from public life
and devote ourselves to prayer and meditation in seclusion, has a
place in most religions, certainly Islam and Christianity. But it is
the exception rather than the rule. When people in open societies
debate public issues with a moral dimension – abortion, for
example, or the death penalty, even taxation and national security –
their religious beliefs are bound to be factors in the debate. If
people choose to take their guidance on these matters from their
religious leaders, they should be free to do so. Even if their
religious beliefs, as formulated by those leaders, are the sole
determinant in the political decisions they take – for example, to
vote against easy abortion or stem cell research – they should not
feel compelled to 'invent' other, non-religious justifications for
their decisions. “The Pope says so” is a good enough reason.
People often make political decisions on grounds that might seem
trivial or thoughtless to others. In a free society where significant
numbers of people hold religious beliefs there is no practical
alternative to this approach. To argue that people must put their
religious beliefs aside when they take political decisions is an
absurdity.
3.2.2 (in response to assumption 2.2.2)
The possibility that religious hierarchies will make unrealistic
demands on the political choices of believers is real and can lead
to tensions in the public sphere. But in practice, even where
religious leaders have been given formal roles, in the constitution
for example, they have rarely dared to assert themselves politically
beyond what the public and politicians will bear. Religious leaders
who are also political actors tend to be acutely tuned to the level
of public support they can muster. If levels of religious belief
decline in society as a whole, religious leaders find it hard to
resist making doctrinal concessions designed to keep waverers within
their flock. In the end, it is believers who empower religious
leaders, not religious leaders who unilaterally impose orthodoxy. If
citizens disagree with religious leaders, they must have the courage
to speak out, not seek devious ways to silence or marginalize the
religious leaders.
3.2.3 (in response to argument 1.2.3)
The argument that religious leaders should not be allowed to overrule
the will of the people is a strong one, the best of all the reasons
cited above. But this represents an extreme case of religious
activism in the political sphere. It is in effect an argument against
giving religious leaders a veto over political decisions, not an
argument for denying them or their followers any voice in political
debate.
3.2.4 (in response to assumption 2.2.3)
Very few governments continue to impose sectarian identities on
their citizens. The governments of majority-Muslim countries are
unique in this regard, as far as I am aware. The practice whereby
Muslim citizens remain Muslim for life and their children inherit
their Muslimness is an outrageous violation of the rights of citizens
and should be abolished as soon as possible. Those who advocate
maintaining this system while simultaneously advocating the exclusion
of religion from politics are hypocrites and/or cowards. Abolition of
this system, a vestige of the Ottoman millet system, will
automatically make the religious hierarchies more responsive to the
beliefs of their followers, who would no longer be a captive
audience. It would go some way towards creating a free market-place
of ideas, where religions and other ideologies could compete for
adherents on a level playing field.
3.2.5 (in response to assumption
2.2.4) There are no objectively valid grounds for discriminating
between political parties with religious agendas and those with
wholly secular agendas. So many gradations between the two are
possible that any conceivable legislation that attempts to
discriminate must open the field to subjective and whimsical
interpretations of the law, which tend to bring the judicial system
into disrepute. Egypt's attempts in this area over the last three
years illustrate the impossibility of the task. Some Egyptian
advocates of excluding religion from politics continue nonetheless to
favour maintaining Islam as the country's state religion. This
contradiction undermines their case from the start. For political
purposes, religion is just another ideology. If religious rivals want
to take their disputes into the political arena they should be free
to do so, provided they refrain from violence or incitement to
violence, as in any country where the rule of law prevails. In
practice, political parties rarely choose to adopt exclusively
sectarian agendas, for the reason that they want to win as many votes
as possible.
3.2.6 (in response to assumption 2.2.5)
Similarly, attempts to exclude religious references from political
discourse are doomed to failure and will bring the judicial system
into disrepute. To take the simplest example, the old National
Democratic Party of Hosni Mubarak, although never actively Islamist,
always arranged that its candidates had the crescent moon as their
symbol on ballot papers. NDP organizers knew this gave them extra
votes because of the positive Islamic associations of the crescent
moon. Enforcing a ban on such religious references would require
thorough monitoring of all campaign literature and all campaign
speeches by all candidates – an unrealistic proposal. Besides, as
we discussed in 3.2.1, religious belief is a legitimate factor in
political decision-making.
4.1 In conclusion, the proposal to
exclude religion from politics is misguided and impractical. Many of
those who advocate this approach are likely to be people of vaguely
deistic beliefs who want to use the political system and the security
state to dilute the power of the religious hierarchies and reduce the
electoral impact of the political forces that advocate obedience to
those hierarchies. Even if one sympathizes with their long-term
goals, one must find fault with their approach, which looks like a
quick fix that seeks to achieve their objectives while conveniently
avoiding open confrontation with the views they oppose.
No comments:
Post a Comment